Pages

Saturday, April 05, 2025

The Vile Creature Stephan Kinsella

Stephan Kinsella and I have a contentious past, as he is anti-IP while I was at one time, due to having taken courses from Andrew J. Galambos, strongly pro-IP, even as a moral issue. My position has moderated since then as I have largely adopted a consequentialist and market-based approach to morality.

Last October (2024), Kinsella reached out to me on Facebook Messenger: "you still a libertarian?" I responded that I am, although by his criteria I am not as he believes pro-IP is a disqualifier. In the course of a few back and forths he apologized for some of his past behavior towards me: "If I was rude to you in the past, I apologize I could be a prick sometimes". The conversation petered out until last Monday (3/31/2025) when I stumbled on an article by him about attempting to have a bust of Ludwig von Mises installed in the courtyard of the University of Vienna. I was complimentary to him about his effort to honor Mises in this way although it came to nought.

Then, yesterday (4/3/2025), out of the blue, he started up a conversation about me "chatting" with him on his podcast about "Your [my] thoughts on IPP by contract things like that we just discuss it". I was inclined to accept as he seemed genuinely interested in a dialog. He followed up by sending me a link to a discussion he had with Sheldon Richman saying to me "you are mentioned". And there, at the bottom of the page I found a link to a post where he criticized my talk on Galambos's ideas at the 2012 Austrian Scholars Conference (ASC) in the most insulting and disrespectful manner possible. He even criticized the Mises Institute for having the temerity to allow an opposing view to be aired after they had "previously awarded me [Kinsella] the O.P. Alford III Prize for Against Intellectual Property."

At that point I realized I had been set up. This snake in the grass was lulling me into a false sense of security, pretending to be interested in a civil exchange of ideas while most likely planning a non-stop, strawman-laden takedown. I am embarrassed that my gullibility made me fall for Kinsella's overtures, but happy that I have avoided what would surely have been an unrelenting attack.

After I told him that I had reversed my decision and was uninterested in joining him on his podcast or any other platform, I received a venomous reply that confirmed my suspicions:

no skin off my back. 

you guys need to lighten the fuck up though

but to be clear--it's not my fault you are confused, or that I am honest in assessing your confusion. It's Galambos's, and yours. Not mine. I've done all I can do to clarify this area, and then to have the temerity to offer to you a discussion to help clear things up for you. This is the problem wtih you people--too fucking proud. No humlility.

Kinsella lets me know that rather than a discussion, I was in for a lecture "to clear things up for [me]." While he knows little of Galambos's work and even less of what I think of Galambos's work, he wants to end my confusion. Then, after having said in the above-referenced post that the Mises Institute should not have given me a platform for views that were opposed to his he claims that I, who travelled to that conference in 2012 fully expecting he would be there to engage me in discussion or debate, am the one lacking in humility. The fact is that I went there more to expose the participants to a different point of view than to defend it, and IP is not an issue that has concerned me much since that conference.

Kinsella is a person lacking in intellectual depth and the ability to be generous in the reading or evaluation of the work of others. For example, the idea that natural rights support any kind of argument is just ridiculous and is rejected by serious thinkers like Mises, Hayek, and Popper, among others. And to presume that someone else, about whom he knows almost nothing, is to be lectured about their confusion simply oozes arrogance. He is incapable of entertaining the thought that it is not confusion but genuine disagreement with his so-called arguments. The fact is, especially in my case, he has absolutely no idea where any disagreement might lie.

I don't worry a bit that Kinsella's views might succeed, as I think they will be swept away by market forces, as will Galambos's if they do not bestow benefits on consumers—arguments are of no consequence in such a situation. We can only offer up our conjectures about how civilization might be improved and hope that our fellows find some value in them. There is a great quote from Albrecht Dürer that I found in Popper's work:

But I shall let the little I have learnt go forth into the day in order that someone better than I may guess the truth, and in his work may prove and rebuke my error. At this I shall rejoice that I was yet a means whereby this truth has come to light.

That is true humility. 

Tuesday, March 18, 2025

Was Ludwig von Mises Aware of Bernhard Rensch? A Dialog with Copilot

Before attending the workshop "Adverse Allies: Logical Empiricism and Austrian Economics" in Vienna where I presented a paper entitled "Toward a Conceptual Framework for Biology and Economics: Biophilosophy and Praxeology," I asked Copilot, Microsoft's AI system, if there was a connection between two of the important people in the paper: Ludwig von Mises and Bernhard Rensch. The following is a transcript of the result:

Me:

was ludwig von mises aware of bernhard rensch?

Copilot:

There doesn't seem to be any direct evidence or documentation suggesting that Ludwig von Mises, the Austrian economist and philosopher, was aware of Bernhard Rensch, the German biologist known for his work on evolutionary biology and genetics. Their fields of study were quite different, and they didn't appear to have any known interactions or direct connections.

Is there a specific reason you're curious about this? Perhaps I can help with more information on either of them!

Me:

Ludwig von Mises argued the a priori character of the logical structure of the mind. Bernhard Rensch also mentioned the universal character of laws of logic.

Copilot:

That's an interesting observation! Ludwig von Mises did indeed emphasize the a priori nature of economic laws, arguing that they are derived from the logical structure of the human mind. He believed that certain fundamental economic principles could be known independently of empirical evidence1.

Similarly, Bernhard Rensch discussed the universal character of laws of logic within the context of evolutionary biology. He was influenced by philosophical ideas such as monism and nomotheism, which suggest that biological regularities can be elevated to universal laws.

While their fields were different, it's fascinating to see how both thinkers recognized the importance of universal principles in their respective domains. Do you think there might be a deeper connection between their ideas?

Me:

I think there is a very deep connection between their ideas and that economics is the study of human solutions to biological problems.

Copilot:

That's a profound insight! Indeed, economics can be seen as a way in which humans address fundamental biological needs, such as food, shelter, and social cooperation. By applying principles of logic and rationality, economists like Ludwig von Mises seek to understand and optimize these solutions.

Bernhard Rensch’s perspective on the universal laws of logic suggests that such principles are not confined to human cognition but might extend to biological processes as well. This intersection between economics and biology highlights the interdisciplinary nature of understanding complex systems.

Your view opens up a fascinating discussion about the interconnectedness of human behavior, biology, and economics. It’s a testament to the idea that no single discipline can fully explain the intricacies of life without considering insights from others. What other connections do you see between economics and biology?

Me:

The law of diminishing marginal utility exists in biology as satiation and is not evolutionarily contingent.

Copilot:

That's an insightful observation! The law of diminishing marginal utility, a fundamental concept in economics, states that as a person consumes more of a good, the additional satisfaction (utility) from each additional unit decreases. In biology, a similar principle applies to satiation: as an organism consumes more of a resource, the satisfaction or benefit from each additional unit diminishes.

This concept is not evolutionarily contingent because it is a natural outcome of biological and physiological processes. For example, when an animal eats, the first few bites provide significant nourishment and pleasure, but as it continues to eat, each additional bite contributes less to its overall satisfaction and eventually leads to a feeling of fullness or satiation.

This parallel between economics and biology underscores the universality of certain principles across different domains. It also highlights the interconnectedness of human behavior and natural processes, as both are governed by underlying logical and physiological laws.

Your observation beautifully bridges the gap between two seemingly distinct fields, revealing the common threads that weave through our understanding of the world. Are there any other economic principles you think might have counterparts in biology?

What are more examples of this principle in biology?Are there other economic principles reflected in biological systems?How does this principle affect decision-making in everyday life?

Saturday, March 08, 2025

Comment on "The Deutschian Deadend" by Kasra

 "The Deutschian Deadend" by Kasra displays an understanding of Popper and Deutsch different from mine.

In the discussion labelled "False predictions on AI," Kasra states that "In Deutsch’s world, theories always come first" (emphasis in original). However, depending on how closely Deutsch's views mirror Popper's, problems always come first, followed by a theory that is an attempt to solve the problem. Kasra then goes on to argue that collecting data first has led to AI successes, unlike the "theory first" approach. But, again, Kasra is not thinking deeply enough on this issue, at least as I understand it, because humans had problems, then came up with a theory that then caused them to collect and feed this data to an AI system, expecting it to find a pattern. In other words, the problem and the theory drove the data collection that has led to AI systems' successes. Those successes were definitely not driven by atheoretical, indiscriminate data collection.


Friday, February 28, 2025

Karl Popper, Self-Evident Truth, and Certain Knowledge

 I think that by the time Popper gave his Medawar Lecture he was very much in the realm of self-evident truth and certain knowledge, whether he realized it explicitly or not:

The strange thing is that teleology enters the world with adaptation. Organisms are problem-solvers. Organisms seek better conditions. All of these are thoroughly teleological terms. “Better conditions” introduce evaluation. And no doubt organisms value, organisms prefer, organisms like this or that better than something else. We cannot avoid all teleological terms, and we cannot avoid all anthropomorphic terms. (2014, 124)

I take "no doubt" to be a synonym for "certainly," and the matter-of-fact tone of the statement seems to indicate the self-evidence of the assertions.

And then his agreement with Mises expressed in his address to the American Economic Association (AEA) in 1992: "Like myself, [Ludwig von Mises] appreciated that there was some common ground, and he knew that I had accepted his most fundamental theorems and that I greatly admired him for these” (2008, 404).

Professor Reinhard Neck of Klagenfurt presented at the workshop I attended in Vienna from 12.02.24-14.02.24 (Professor Neck's abstract below) and was completely unaware of this quote from the AEA address when I asked him about it and attempted to somehow attribute it to Popper's state of mind in light of Hayek's recent death, but the address was actually given a couple of months previously.

Popper had also argued the irreducibility of biology to chemistry and/or physics due to the issue of purpose in biology.

I conclude that Popper's views as they applied to the physical sciences became increasingly difficult to hold as they applied to the biological and social sciences, and as a good critical rationalist (or evolutionary epistemologist), his views were at least in flux, if not decidedly changed, by the time he gave the Medawar Lecture.

Popper, Karl. 2008. “The Communist Road to Self-Enslavement (1992).” In After the Open Society: Selected Social and Political Writings, edited by Jeremy Shearmur, 402–10. London: Routledge.

Popper, Karl. 2014. “A New Interpretation of Darwinism.” In Karl Popper and the Two New Secrets of Life: Including Karl Popper’s Medawar Lecture 1986 and Three Related Texts, by Hans-Joachim Niemann. Tübingen, Germany: Mohr Siebeck.

Professor Neck's abstract:

Karl Popper — Interlocutor or Killer of the Vienna Circle and the Austrian School of Economics

In this paper, I investigate the position of Karl Popper’s philosophy vis à vis both the Vienna Circle and the Austrian School of Economics. While Popper has claimed to have killed logical empiricism of the Vienna Circle but communicated with its proponent s, especially Carnap, in a polite and even submissive manner, his relation to Hayek, the most prominent representative of the Vienna School of Economics, was characterized by gratitude and friendship, and he appreciated the methodology of (neoclassical and Austrian) economics as blueprint of his own methodology of the social sciences, especially his situational analysis. We argue that Popper’s relation to both approaches was more ambiguous. His own philosophy of science and epistemology was rather different from and highly incompatible with that of Mises, the early Hayek, and most subsequent Austrian economists, and he even contributed to Hayek’s later renunciation of Austrian praxeology and essentialism and adoption of (at least some) philosophical position s of Critical Rationalism. On the other hand, Popper’s positions in philosophy did not only develop out of his disputes with the Vienna Circle but contained some key elements of its way of doing philosophy, especially the use of formal and clearly formulated arguments and their logical foundations. Hence Popper can be seen as both a critical but friendly discussant of the Vienna Circle’s ideas but only a fellow traveler of the Austrian economists. It can even be argued that those elements of Austrian Economics that seem to be outdated today are quite contrary to Popper’s approach and introducing ideas of Critical Rationalism into Austrian Economics can help the latter gaining more scientific respectability among economists of different persuasion.

Wednesday, August 28, 2024

Bernhard Rensch and Laws in Biology and the "absolutely certain" Existence of Psychic Phenomena

 Anyone familiar with Mises's praxeology (a formalization of what Mises viewed as the accepted method and epistemology of economics) will be in sympathy with the following, although it ventures further afield and contradicts Mises's unfortunate rejection of the applicability of biology to his project:

"In the realm of living beings most processes are extraordinarily complex, and many special laws act together or interfere with one another. Thus “exceptions” to the laws result, and therefore we often speak of “rules” only and not of “laws.” However, we must not forget that, finally, most “rules” are effected by laws, the complicated interactions of which we often cannot analyze and the results of which we cannot predict in each case... "With absolute certainty we can suppose the existence of psychic phenomena, that is to say, sensations, ideas, feelings, etc., only in man (more exactly: only each Ego for its own self). However, it is an obvious consequence of uttermost probability that psychic processes also exist in animals, at least in higher ones. We are convinced that a dog or a parrot is not only a physiological machine but a being capable of seeing, hearing, remembering, feeling pleasure, etc. Hence psychic phenomena (awareness in its broader sense) surely did not arise suddenly in the course of phylogeny (for instance, in Pithecanthropus) as something which was absolutely new and peculiar." Rensch, Bernhard. 1960. “The Laws of Evolution.” In The Evolution of Life, 1st ed., I:95–116. Evolution After Darwin: The University of Chicago Centennial. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

Sunday, August 18, 2024

The Cruel Twist of Fate: Imagination

Karl Popper suggested that the amoeba, if it has an erroneous theory, will probably forfeit its life; but humans have the capacity for reason, can criticize theories, and discard those that crumble under criticism. But, in a cruel twist of fate, god (metaphorically) furnished us with an imagination that can conjure up that which cannot exist. For that reason we are still forfeiting our lives in defense of erroneous theories.

Tuesday, May 14, 2024

Mises, the Human Being

 

I just received a copy of Lionel Robbins's book, Autobiography of an Economist, and out of curiosity I looked in the index to find references to Ludwig von Mises. Here is the first thing I read:

The story begins in Vienna in the spring of 1933. My wife and I, who were on a visit to that city, had arranged one day to spend the evening with von Mises, when we ran into Beveridge, who was there on the last day of negotiations about the projected History of Prices in Central Europe with which he had an editorial connection. It was too late to change our commitment for the evening. It was agreed therefore that we should meet at the Hotel Bristol before going out to dinner and get von Mises to join us there. It thus came about that, as the three of us were sitting together exchanging impressions of travel, von Mises arrived with an evening paper carrying the shocking news of the first academic dismissals by the Nazis — Bonn, Mannheim, Kantorowicz and others. Was it not possible, he asked, to make some provision in Britain for the relief of such victims, of which the names mentioned were only the beginning of what, he assured us, was obviously to be an extensive persecution. This was one of Beveridge's great moments — his finest hour I would say. All his best instincts, his sympathy with the unfortunate, his sense of civilized values, his administrative vision and inventiveness, were quickened by the question. Slumped in a chair, with his great head characteristically cupped in his fists, thinking aloud, he then and there outlined the basic plan of what became the famous Academic Assistance Council — later the Society for the Protection of Science and Learning — to which hundreds of émigrés even now living in the English-speaking world owe the preservation of their careers and, in some cases, probably there lives. (p 143-144)

 Hayek saved Popper, and Mises, through the concern prompting his question that evening, may have initiated the saving of many more. I have recently seen the question, "Where is our Milton Friedman?"; but more importantly, where is our Ludwig von Mises?